-
Recent Posts
Archives
- November 2024
- October 2024
- February 2024
- March 2023
- April 2021
- September 2020
- November 2019
- February 2019
- October 2018
- December 2017
- May 2017
- June 2016
- September 2015
- March 2015
- August 2014
- December 2013
- July 2013
- December 2012
- July 2012
- December 2011
- August 2011
- December 2010
- June 2010
- December 2009
- July 2009
- December 2008
- June 2008
- December 2007
- October 2007
- August 2007
- December 2006
- August 2006
- May 2006
- December 2005
- April 2005
- December 2004
- May 2004
- October 2003
- February 2003
- October 2002
- August 2002
- March 1999
- June 1994
- September 1992
- January 1990
Categories
- abortion
- Against Separatism
- alaska
- anarchy
- anchorage anarchy
- animals and plants
- Apio Ludd
- Bad Press
- Benjamin Tucker
- Broadsides
- capitalism
- communism
- death penalty
- draft resistance
- drugs
- Ed Stamm
- education
- Elayne Riggs
- Emile Armand
- environment
- Errico Malatesta
- free speech
- global warming
- guns
- health care
- identity
- imperialism
- individualism
- insurrection
- Iris Mills
- Jason Rodgers
- Jo Labadie
- Joe Peacott
- John Zube
- Josiah Warren
- Karl Hess
- kids
- labor
- land
- leftism
- Lysander Spooner
- madness
- Makhno
- Malcolm X
- Mark Twain
- Maureen Flannery
- Max Stirner
- Michael Schmidt
- migration
- Modern Times
- Mollie Steimer
- multiculturalism
- mutualism
- nationalism
- Nicholas Evans
- Nigel Meek
- Peter Cariani
- Peter Lamborn Wilson
- platformism
- police
- poverty
- property
- psychiatry
- racism
- Ralph Nimmo
- religion
- resistance
- Richard Garner
- Robert McCracken
- Rosa Luxemburg
- Ruth Hubbard
- science
- SE Parker
- Senya Fleshin
- sex
- spain
- Stephen Pearl Andrews
- syndicalism
- The Individual
- Thomas Szasz
- Total Liberty/Anarchist Voices
- Voline
- voting
- war
- work
Category Archives: capitalism
Against Sustainability
Recently I’ve found myself wishing—when I hear the word “sustainability”—that I had a revolver to reach for. “Sustainability” has become a coded mask for a cause I detest—the salvation of Capitalism. Obviously, Too-Late Kapital is running down the road to “global” ragnarok, and has been doing so since the great take-off of the Technopathocracy in about 1830 (when, according to HG Wells, “the first superfluous human was born”)—ie, the Industrial Revolution, the triumph of the Machine over Nature. Nietzsche dated the birth of the Terminal Human to about this same date; so the first shall be the last.
The whole point of sustainability is to save cars, but re-design them to run on sunshine or salad oil—to save highways, parking lots, jet planes, suburban lawns, bourgeois yuppie liberal smug self-satisfaction and “first world” entitlement—but to transform them all into something beige, crunchy, “ecological,” “organic,” smiley–faced, goodygoody—and to go on like this forever—“sustainably.” To avoid the Fall, even if it means abandoning huge swathes of the human race and its habitat, so as to salvage the part that counts—US—or put another way, US (of A). To escape to Mars with Mr Musk in a driverless spaceship “shared” by other billionaires, and fuck all hoi polloi and their degraded junkfood “lifestyle.”
Solar power and wind power, the panaceae of sustainability, are themselves source of vast hellscapes of aesthetic filth and poisonous pollution—the factories (in Mexico, of course) to produce those ubiquitous alien-gray panels and war-of-the-worlds-style windmills (impervious to any poor Don Quixote)—to cover the deserts with black glass, the seas with whining avicidal behemoths—so that WE can go on enjoying our horrid health-food, our idiotic iPhones, our crapulous computers, our tedious televisions—not to mention our armies and police forces, our bureaucrats, politicians, lawyers, silicon-valley “disruptors” and all the other parasites and oppressor-class scumbags who take but never give.
Forget sustainability. Forget efficiency. Efficiency is the devil’s shit. Fuck “green capitalism” and its neat corporate cornucopia of consumer garbage and badly-designed “designer” crapola. Technology will not solve the “problems” that technology created in the first place, any more than heroin will cure morphine addiction, or arsenic will save you from arsenic poisoning. The only way to free ourselves from the rule of sick machines is to smash the machines. The Luddites saw the light already in 1812. A sledgehammer is the sole solution.
A Brief Review of Wm Gary Kline’s The Individualist Anarchists: A Critique of Liberalism
Kline wrote a very interesting book called The Individualist Anarchists and it does have some useful information that can improve understanding of the philosophy of the 19th century Individualist Anarchists. He mentions Stephen Pearl Andrews, Lysander Spooner, William Greene, Benjamin Tucker and others and portrays them in an accurate light. He correctly refers to them as Voluntary Socialists or Socialists as he states:
“…but Voluntary Socialists were in unanimity concerning the issue of monopolies in general…”[i]
He also stated Tucker considered Josiah Warren, who was an Individualist Anarchist, to be a Socialist.[ii]
However in a very interesting (and confusing) twist he considers the Individualists Anarchists to be liberals rather than what they truly are: socialists. He refers to the Individualist Anarchist philosophy as liberal many times. Some examples include:
“The brand of liberalism to which these libertarians adhered had some uncommon strengths and weaknesses.”[iii]
“The point is that the Individualist Anarchists challenged not the premises of the Classical Liberal tradition, but only those practical aspects which they considered to be perversions or distortions of the values at the core at that tradition.”[iv]
“Though they were a radical variant of the predominant liberal tradition in America, rather than a radical alternative…”[v]
It seems to me Kline considers any market system as liberal whether it is actually socialist or not.
Of course Kline’s view on markets does not reflect reality. Markets can be socialist. Kline would have to ignore the entire socialist movement when making such a claim.
For instance, Proudhon, the first to call himself an anarchist, spoke of a socialist system of Mutualism based on co-operatives in a competitive market. Many individualist anarchists would agree with Proudhon and his view of co-operatives in a competitive market. Would Kline consider Proudhon a liberal? It appears it could be so if his definition of liberalism is any system that contains competitive markets.
So what is Liberalism? Liberalism is a philosophy that encourages property and free markets, as Kline rightly claims, but Liberalism contains a specific type of market, more specifically capitalist free markets. Hence, Proudhon distinguished between property and possession in his What is Property?[vi]—in other words, the difference between capitalist markets and non-capitalist competitive markets with possession instead of property.
Kline points out correctly that profit and usury are essential aspects of capitalism which he points out are what the Individualist Anarchists critique.[vii] Kline, however, does not consider the fact that it is precisely that critique that makes the Individualist Anarchists Socialist.
As Marx states, the essential aspect of Capitalism is called Surplus Value, or what amounts to making an income without working for it. Surplus Value (called usury) is unearned profit, interest and rent. However, even landlordism, while a form of surplus value, is not capitalist but a form of feudalism. What specifically distinguishes Capitalism from other market systems, such as Mutualism and Individualist Anarchist socialist markets, is that within Capitalism employers pay their employees less than the full value of their labor and there is not equality of opportunity on the market.
Within Capitalism labor in general is not factored into the price of the product. Within the market socialism of the Individualist Anarchists labor is in general factored into the prices of products and there is equality of opportunity on the market through mutual banks, which would offer credit at a price of 1% or less to cover overhead. The low rates offered by mutual banks would ensure that people would have the option of going into business for themselves. Therefore, employers would have to raise their wages to entice workers to work for them. Hence, wages would rise to the full product of a worker’s labor.[viii]
This is what distinguishes market socialism from capitalism.
As Marx states:
“The working day of 12 hours is represented in a monetary value of, for example, 6 shillings. There are two alternatives. Either equivalents are exchanged, and then the worker receives 6 shillings for 12 hours of labour; the price of his labour would be equal to the price of his product. In that case he produces no surplus-value for the buyer of his labour, the 6 shillings are not transformed into capital, and the basis of capitalist production vanishes.”[ix]
The unearned income is called Surplus Value. Markets do not equate capitalism which is why different market systems like market socialism and Mutualism exist.
Tucker’s way of organizing business would be similar to a capitalist business with employers and employees. However, the difference between a capitalist business and Tucker’s Individualist Anarchist business would be that in the Individualist Anarchist business, employers and employees would be paid the full value of their labor depending on the going rate of the occupation on the Individualist Anarchist market at the time. In addition, the Individualist Anarchist market would have equality of opportunity on the market due to the Mutual Banks.[x]
Tucker agreed with Marx on his theory of surplus value which can be seen in his article ‘Karl Marx Friend and Foe.’[xi] This is why Benjamin Tucker who supported non-exploitive employers (and whom Kline labeled the representative of Individualist Anarchism[xii]) called himself correctly an Anarchist-Socialist.[xiii]
While Kline gives a very good and accurate historical overview of Individualist Anarchist theory, at the same time, for reasons I am not aware of, he chooses to ignore socialist history and socialist theory (including that of Marx). Instead, he dismisses market socialism and Individualist Anarchist theory in general by labeling the Individualist Anarchists incorrectly as liberal rather than what they truly are: market socialists.
[i] Kline, Wm Gary, The Individualist Anarchists. University Press of America. (1987) p 72
[ii] Ibid, p 72
[iii] Ibid, p 93
[iv] Ibid. p 104
[v] Ibid, p 104
[vi] Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph, What is Property?
[vii] Marx, Karl, The Communist Manifesto
[viii] Tucker, Benjamin, State Socialism and Anarchism.
[ix] Marx, Karl, Capital Volume 1. England: Penguin Classics (reprint). (1990) p 676
[x] Tucker, Benjamin, Instead of a Book. Forgotten Books. (2012) p 3-18
[xi] Ibid, p 477
[xii] Kline, Wm Gary, The Individualist Anarchists. University Press of America. (1987) p 1
[xiii] Tucker, Instead of a Book.
Defending Anarchy
Several people have recently said to me—half-jokingly—“You anarchists must be happy now that the Republicans are dismantling the government!”
I’m afraid I replied angrily and bitterly that such a remark (even half in jest) represents a serious misunderstanding about the nature of anarchism, which—in all its varieties—includes a strong critique of any form of hegemonic oppression by any kind of “authority.” Continue reading
To Market, To Market
In a review of anchorage anarchy in a recent edition of Anarchy, A Journal of Desire Armed, I am described by the author as a “non-anti-capitalist anarchist.” Around the same time I read this article, I also received a letter from a contributor to aa in which I was called to task for my use of the word market to describe the sort of economic relations I think would best serve free people. While the Anarchy writer did not elaborate on why he chose the description he did, my correspondent did go on to say that he thinks “free people would determine the means of exchange/sharing/distribution that is most suitable for them & it would tend to be disorganized and fluid, where market implies a more structured approach.” Continue reading
Anarchy, Neither Capitalist nor Communist
Jason’s article on Stirner and capitalism later in this issue serves to clarify an important point which too many anarchists fail to recognize; that opposition to collectivist economic and social arrangements does not make one a supporter of capitalism. Stirner and most other egoists and individualists have been at least as critical of capitalist economic relations as they have been of capitalism’s socialist and communist critics. But this very consistent and clear individualist opposition to capitalism throughout the history of the movement, from Stirner through Tucker and Warren to the Mackay Society and Bad Press seems to have been missed by some of our critics on the left of the anarchist movement.
Partly this is because at least some of us write and talk about markets, money and prices as viable devices to guide economic and social relationships in a stateless world. We defend private property and tenure of land and living quarters based on use and occupancy. We believe individuals do not owe anything to anyone else unless they freely entered into an agreement with other folks to cooperate in some project or exchange some goods or services. Apparently, since we use some of the same words as do supporters of capitalism, there are those in the libertarian movement who would group us with them.
But we also condemn profit, rent, interest, and intellectual property. And we believe that none of these methods of extorting wealth from productive people and transferring it to the rich would be possible without the existence of the band of armed thugs who defend economic inequity, ie, government in its various forms, and we therefore oppose the state and all forms of authority as well. We support workers’ control and ownership of their workplaces and what they produce. We support squatting of unused living spaces. And we support any form of social interaction, whether cooperative or competitive, which is freely chosen and from which one is free to walk away when they so choose. This sounds like no form of capitalism with which I am familiar.
What’s in a Name?
While much of the anarchist movement defines itself by its opposition to capitalism, it fails to show a similar level of contempt for socialism and communism. In fact, many anarchists continue to identify themselves as anarchist communists or libertarian socialists. By doing so they demonstrate a belief that the real-world examples of socialist and communist societies with which we are all familiar, so-called “actually existing socialism,” are not the only kind of socialist societies that are possible. And this is despite the fact that the socialist societies created since the russian revolution have been at least as tyrannical, murderous and exploitative as any capitalist society could ever hope to be. Yet, they find it acceptable to label their movement and their ideas with the same words used by Stalin and Mao to describe the abattoirs they ruled.
There has never been a real world socialist/communist society that could be mistaken for anything approaching an anarchy. And I am not speaking here just of the marxist-leninist states like the ussr, china, or korea. The various flavors of african socialism, whether in Nkrumah’s ghana or Nyerere’s tanzania were all authoritarian as well, even if less brutal than those in europe and asia.
Furthermore, in the few instances where supposedly anarchist communists were in a position to help build libertarian societies, as in spain in the thirties and the ukraine around 1920, the anarchists acted like authoritarians. While they were quick to dismantle capitalist economic structures, they were far less interested in destroying the state and other authoritarian institutions. They had armies with command structures, conscription and even the death penalty. There were leaders and followers. These were not anarchist societies.
A Curse on Both Your Houses
Capitalism as we know it is loathsome. But so is socialism as we know it. Anarchist communists say that the socialist countries were and are examples of authoritarian socialism, while they work towards a libertarian socialism which will look entirely different. But they are deaf to the arguments of individualists who say that the free markets, free exchange, and free trade we advocate have nothing in common with authoritarian capitalism. Anything that resembles, in their minds, capitalism is not acceptable.
Reading the anarchist press one often finds far more criticism of capitalism than of the state. And such antigovernment sentiment often seems an afterthought. Such a focus on opposing capitalism, and prioritizing that over a critique of government and authority itself, is what leads so many anarchists to applaud authoritarian leftist militias like the zapatistas and the sandinistas before them, to wear (and sell) t-shirts bearing the image of Che, and to talk approvingly of Mondragón which is riddled with authority and inequity and often acts like any traditional capitalist enterprise. I fail to see how support for authoritarian means will produce libertarian ends.
The State and Revolution
Although I favor individualist arrangements over collectivist ones, I believe that people should be free to partner with others in any sort of social or economic activity they choose, as long as no coercion is involved. And the only way to rid the world of coercion is to eliminate the state and other authoritarian institutions. Anarchists, whether socialist or individualist, need to be promoting this message.
We all oppose the various flavors of authoritarian government around the world, whether capitalist or (at least nominally) socialist. But when the government of the united states is criticized by anarchists it is often as an agent of capitalists, while the soviet government would never have been attacked by libertarians as a representative of communists, despite the fact that that is what its rulers called themselves. In both the old ussr and today’s usa, quite different authoritarian societies and economies were/are imposed on unwilling victims. Such subjugation is not a function of any particular economic system, it is a result of a political system, of a state.
That is the message that anarchists should be sending out. The anarchists of europe long ago separated themselves from the rest of the socialist movement because they believed that the state was at the root of the problems experienced by working people. Their critique of government and authority—at least on paper—was what distinguished them from the authoritarians in the movement of their day. Unfortunately, today’s anarchist left seems far more interested in being part of the anti-capitalist opposition that in offering an anarchist critique of both that movement and the state. That does not bode well for the future of freedom.
Stirner and Capitalism
There is a curious statement in Robert Anton Wilson and Robert Shea’s novel Illuminatus!:
“Most anarchists hoped Joachim-like, to redistribute the wealth, but Rebecca had once told him about a classic of anarchist literature, Max Stirner’s The Ego and His Own, which has been called ‘the Billionaire’s Bible’ because it stressed the advantages the rugged individualist would gain in a stateless society.” (53)
For those of us who have read Stirner, this is an odd statement. It might be assumed that this was purposeful, one of Wilson’s guerrilla ontology tactics, and that it was put forward in such a manner only to later deconstruct its underlying assumptions. Of course, equally possible it was meant at face value, particularly considering Wilson’s soft spot for free-market libertarianism and capitalism. This sort of view of Stirner, and egoism in general, is an all too common assumption. Stirner is often viewed as a proponent of an extreme form of anarcho-capitalism. This view, however, is unfounded.
There is a common misconception that Stirner was some sort of rogue capitalist. Certainly some of his disciples have contributed to this notion. In his writings, Stirner rarely ventured into the realm of economics. When he did so it was to dispel the spooks of economics. He argued that people by nature are egoists, and that ideologies to the contrary merely serve as rationalization and justification for egoism. It would be better to be honest about motivation. It has been common for some to equate this viewpoint with capitalism. The underlying assumption made by many is that capitalism is individualist, thus Stirner supported capitalism. This is not what Stirner said.
Most of Stirner’s concepts and projects were negative, that is they were intended to break down structures and ideologies. One of the few positive projects he proposed is the “Union of Egoists”(79), which he did not really define. By nature this union could not be strictly defined, as it is fluid, open and dynamical. It was a proposal for individuals to come together with others, in a fashion that does not compromise the self, but rather amplifies it. He never proposed that individuals should not work together or share. On the contrary, friendship may be one of the most powerful egoist tools. The egoist can give up many things for friendship, as Stirner argued:
“I can with joy sacrifice to him numberless enjoyments, I can deny myself numberless things for the enhancement of his pleasure, and I can hazard for him what without him was the dearest to me, my life, my welfare, my freedom. Why, it constitutes my pleasure and my happiness to refresh myself with his happiness and his pleasure. But myself, my own self, I do not sacrifice to him, but remain an egoist and – enjoy him”(290).
Some might mistake his skepticism and criticism of alternatives, such as communism, as a defense of capitalism. I don’t think that it is. When he said “If you know a better medium of exchange, go ahead; yet it will be a ‘money’ again”(274), it seems to be a criticism that communism is merely a new form of capitalism. Really, the egoist wants autonomy and liberty for themselves, and the autonomy and liberty of others enhances this. The problems of capitalism, such as division of labor, were dealt with by Stirner, such as when he argued that “if I do not trouble myself about my affair, I must be content with what pleases others to vouchsafe me. To have bread is my affair, my wish and desire, and yet people leave that to the bakers”(275).
The structure of capitalism is not a reflection of individualism or egoism. It isn’t even necessary to refer to Stirner to come to this conclusion. Capitalism relies on a massive structure of manufacturing and social control. It has division of labor at its root. Division of labor is not the same as specialization. Specialization means that a person may have a particular set of skills that they are most adept at, or most enjoy. Division of labor means that each task is broken down into repetitive blocks in order to improve efficiency. A person cannot build a car themselves, they are reliant on a massive megamachine of manufacturing. Even if a person has all the mechanical skills to assemble the pieces, they do not have the capability to manufacture the pieces or to forge the necessary tools or to mine the raw materials for its production. This always relies on a collective form, and of the worst sort. This is a form that has alienation, boredom and even slavery as its component parts.
It may be beneficial to look towards Raoul Vaneigem for some ideas as to how to get out of this position. Vaneigem was one of the primary theorists of the Situationist International, and might have his philosophy defined as egoist communism. He criticized masters not on moral grounds, but because “masters, and God himself, are weak because of the shortcomings of those whom they govern. The master knows the positive role of alienation, the slave its negative one, but both are denied full mastery”(204). Capitalism eliminates the masters, leaving “just slaves-who-consume-power, distin-guishable from one another only by reference to the relative quantity of power they consume”(207). Vaneigem proposed a solution to this problem, the coming of “masters without slaves”(207). In his view, the proletariat should adopt an egoist position and become “the bearer of the end of class distinctions and of hierarchy”(213).
In the end, the egoist is no friend of capitalism. It is another spook to be destroyed. The writing of Stirner reflects this. Yet one doesn’t need Stirner to come to this conclusion, it is obvious when considering the nature of capitalism, the megamachine that turns individuals into components of an artificial system. Petit bourgeois tactics, such as becoming an independent craftsman, may be useful survival strategies on a temporary basis, but make terrible ideologies. The individual is never free under capitalism, even if they get a bigger cubicle. I want to destroy the walls of the cubicle, escape from work and production altogether. I don’t want to do this alone, though. I want a union of egoists to join me. At first a limited union may feel like enough but soon the mere possibility of having to encounter slavery in any form will feel disgusting enough that it will have to be destroyed, just out of fear that it might spread its infection.
Works cited:
Stirner, Max. The Ego and His Own. trans.
Stephen T Byington. Mineola, NY: Dover Publications, 1973, 2005.
Vaneigem, Raoul. The Revolution of Everyday Life. trans. Donald Nicholson-Smith. London, Rebel Press, 1983, 2006.
Wilson, Robert Anton and Robert Shea. The Illuminatus! Trilogy. NY: Dell, 1975, 1988.
Misanthropic philanthropists
Back in June, Warren Buffet announced he would donate $31,000,000,000 to the Gates foundation. While this action generated a lot of favorable publicity, as well as some criticism, for Gates and Buffet, no one seemed overly concerned about where all this money came from.
They made it the old-fashioned way: they stole it. Continue reading